I have been offered a job teaching Introduction to Ethics. I have been given full creative control in designing my course, and while I have not talked to the department, I wanted first to reflect on teaching ethics for myself. Feel free to speak to me about where you also see an Introduction to Ethics course, and its value.
Earlier in the semester, I objected to an Intro to Ethics course I learned about. The Professor had designed it to re-direct the class away from classical theory survey course, and instead, he taught the class under the question of spiritual vocation or calling of the students. Marx and Weber were principal sources of reading for the course. Had the Professor done right by the students? Maybe. I am ambivalent about it. As one might expect, some of the students were ill-prepared to think about their own values in relation to being called in life. The students "didn't get it." In fact, this experience of being-called or acting under a spiritual vocation does not really "catch" the current undergraduate mind as much as thinking of morality in terms of rule-following.
Yet, the class makes sense when we think of how limiting rule-following accounts can be. I prefer virtue-ethics and sympathize with the designer's intention. Yet again, the purpose of an Introduction to Ethics class may serve several functions that prevent what we, as moral philosophers, think about morality. We should be honest about that. Our theoretical approaches might pre-dispose us to teach certain ways over others.
The purpose of an Introduction to Ethics course introduces students to what philosophers have said about living a moral life. In so doing, the practical upshot of this course is that it forces students to reflect on issues in their own life in a systematic way. Ethics can open up reflection in ways that the student never considered. For the philosophy department, the Introduction to Ethics course may serve as a primer for higher courses in applied ethical courses or a higher-level ethical theory courses. If the department views the course in this way, then an implicit harmony of this intention must be reflected in the Introduction to Ethics design. Some departments might view freshman level courses as services courses in the core curriculum and teach the same theories independently of what the Introduction course teaches. If that is so, then I need not worry about its relation to how the department teaches higher-level ethics courses.
If students will never take another ethics class ever again, then it seems reasonable that theoretical survey approaches would be used. Pack as much ethics in as much as possible! Students should learn a good deal of deontology, utilitarianism and virtue ethics. They should study how these approaches can illuminate different cases and find some exploration in applying these methods to cases themselves. However, the theory survey approach can be done in two ways, and by delineating two ways, I do not mean to suggest that these are mutually exclusive. They are not.
First, we can use primary readings of major philosophers. At some places, undergraduates are equipped with the reading skills to do this; other times they are not. Second, we can use someone that has explained the ideas for them. The former can be done through requiring students purchase translations of Kant, Aristotle and Mill, or I can use a historical anthology. Public institutions typically favor keeping the cost down for students and anthologies or cheap translations are used. At SIU, the Dean wants departments to be sensitive to the fact we have the highest amount of grant funded students in the state.
Regarding the latter, I can teach someone like Rachels that puts the ideas together for the student. In such a class, students are removed from the burden of thinking through difficult readings. They are responsible more for getting the relations of the ideas right as someone like Rachels has articulated them in the reading. In this way, I do not teach the content of Kant and Mill from their own words, but how Rachels articulates them. In some ways, this is easier on my end. I am not burdened at lecturing about a philosophical text, but could focus on the arguments as extrapolated by Rachels. I focus more on the ideas, but then again so do the students.
I could supplement teaching philosophy through the use of literature. For instance, I could use Victor Frankl's Man's Search for Meaning or Elie Wiesel's Night. Sometimes, I feel the Holocaust is a bit used and abused. If anybody has thoughts on this, I would love to hear it, and for the record, I do agree with Nussbaum that literature has a place in teaching ethics. I have even heard of a class using Agatha Christie novels.
Next, I could restrict the amount of theory that is done, and devote an entire class to the best approach to ethics. As a virtue ethicist, I cannot help but think that a course on virtue approaches might be the best way to proceed. I could restrict the course to a time period, like Plato's dialogues, Aristotle and some of the Stoics. Then, I could fast-forward to contemporary appropriations of those same themes. Yet, given the other thoughts about the role of Intro to Ethics, the course may serve other functions that such a restriction would be seen as a disservice.
Finally, I have been thinking about the classic three text Introduction to Ethics. I select three texts pitched in a meta-narrative I tell the students. I devote five weeks to in-depth study as to what the philosopher says. Of the three, Nietzsche's Genealogy of Morals is used as the skeptical text. Of the three, I am thinking De Beauvoir, Nietzsche and Kant. I would teach Kant as a person that thinks that morality requires a foundation. Nietzsche would be skeptical of that foundation, and De Beauvoir would articulate an ethics even in light of a lack of foundation--a point that Nietzsche would agree with her on. I would fit these texts together and use the class to tell that story, roughly speaking. On my part, I would say that this is the most avant-garde of how I have imagined teaching this course. The drawback of this selection is that the course must come to a synthesis of the texts relation, and when I do that, I do not necessarily apply those ideas outside of that narrative easily. That might generate two conflicting aims to which the students might confuse, and it might stifle teaching the material.
At most public universities, they teach an anthology that divides up the course into three components: metaethics, normative theory and practical ethics/applied ethics. Let's call this the tripartite conception. For the most part, I find this approach reasonable. It keeps the cost low, and there are several texts that are devoted to this distinction with readings in each of the three sections. Of those that I have seen, Schafer-Landau's books are commonly used. Students get a sense of all the types of moral philosophy. The drawback is that students think about ideas, the readings are analytically dense and eschew the historical side of moral philosophy. As everyone knows, I am devoted to understanding philosophy through its history. I do not know if I could sacrifice that even if I taught a classically analytic and ahistoric approach to moral philosophy.
In summary, I have talked about 4 approaches: theory-survey approach, restricted-theory approach, three-text approach, and the tripartite conception. In addition, I have also talked about some ideas concerning the selection of texts from anthologies, primary authors and to the supplementing these with literary examples. I have not drawn any specific conclusions. Instead, I am leaving it purposefully indeterminate, and invite comments about how best to teach Introduction to Philosophy.
I attempt to overcome the chasm, the divide, between many philosophical traditions. Maintaining traditions that don't talk to any other traditions makes thinking stale.
Friday, April 19, 2013
Le Guin on Libraries
Ursula K. Le Guin has been my favorite writer for years. Before Hogwarts, there was Roke Knoll and Isle of the Wise. Before Raistlin, Ged chased Cobb. Before Butler's performativity of gender, there were the Gethenians. And even Harold Bloom once claimed, emphatically it would seem, "Le Guin, more than Tolkein, has raised fantasy into high literature."
In a book of essays I own by her, The Wave in the Mind: Talks and Essays on the Writer, the Reader and the Imagination, she writes:
Bravo.
In a book of essays I own by her, The Wave in the Mind: Talks and Essays on the Writer, the Reader and the Imagination, she writes:
Plunging into the ocean of words, roaming in the broad fields of the mind, climbing the mountains of the imagination. Just like the kid in the Carnegie or the student in Widener, that was my freedom, that was my joy. And it still is. That joy must not be sold. It must not be privatized, made into another privilege for the privileged. A public library is a public trust. And that freedom must not be compromised. It must be available to all who need it, and that's everyone, when they need it, and that's always. (22-23).
Bravo.
Wednesday, April 17, 2013
Joe Rouse's Paper on Heidegger and Philosophy of Science
Every once in a while, I find a paper that I really enjoy. Joe Rouse's paper on Heidegger and his philosophy of science is a good expansion in an otherwise serious area of neglect.
Tuesday, April 16, 2013
Philosophy Carnival, Again
Again, there is no Continental philosophy at the Philosophy Carnival. There isn't even the bad-analytic-friendly-Heidegger appropriated by Dreyfus to talk about things analytic philosophers care about or some such thing that the main participants might seemingly care about, e.g. naturalized Nietzsche or friendly and critical reception of Foucault. Instead, the Carnival is a celebration of West coast and central plain states people yet again.
Moreover, the only blog posts by women contributors are those blog posts specifically about women observing culture or the profession. There is no substantive blog post about a philosophical issue written by a woman. If the Carnival took seriously Herbert and Kukla's posted blog post, they would have found articles concerning philosophical issues written by women and not re-post what the organizers already know they should be doing. Though to the Carnival's credit, it has picked the two most well-known blogging female philosophers (Kukla and De Cruz), so maybe there is a silver lining in what was picked.
Certainly, there is no tolerance for philosophical pluralism. One might need a good dose of openness in the way that either Gadamer or Dewey talk about being open to experiencing the world.
Moreover, the only blog posts by women contributors are those blog posts specifically about women observing culture or the profession. There is no substantive blog post about a philosophical issue written by a woman. If the Carnival took seriously Herbert and Kukla's posted blog post, they would have found articles concerning philosophical issues written by women and not re-post what the organizers already know they should be doing. Though to the Carnival's credit, it has picked the two most well-known blogging female philosophers (Kukla and De Cruz), so maybe there is a silver lining in what was picked.
Certainly, there is no tolerance for philosophical pluralism. One might need a good dose of openness in the way that either Gadamer or Dewey talk about being open to experiencing the world.
Monday, March 11, 2013
Philosophy Carnival Lacks Any Continental Philosophy And That's A Negative Thing
I have noticed that for the past three months (at least) that the Philosophy Carnival has been fairly dominated by analytic philosophers. Keeping in mind Jeff Malpas recent interview at 3AM...
I think it is time to organize our own Continental philosophy carnival. As Malpas has confirmed, this distinction is not philosophical. Often analytic philosophers use either "family resemblance" or the metaphor of style. I do not think these apply directly. Indirectly sure. These might explain some of what is going on. Yet, the fact is that often what is seen as interesting to analytic conversations could not find purchase in a larger culture due to their neglect of the hermeneutic, phenomenological and pragmatic features of human life and action.
Take for example the entries in this month's carnival.
I have searched since October 2012. There hasn't been one article on a Continental author, not even to Protevi at New APPS that analytics know.
Moreover, Kenny Pearce has been a host of the Carnival several times over, and I feel that the the Carnival circulates in a network of blogs. This might explain how selection bias amongst its organizers avoid Continental philosophy while driving philosophy into oblivion. Having read through a lot of the Carnivals, one could possibly be convinced that there is an endemic of people worried about Plantinga!
the distinction between analytic and continental philosophy is a political distinction. This is important, because we often mistake it for a philosophical distinction. But it isn’t that, at least not primarily, and that is why the ‘discussion’ has been going on for so long (it certainly isn’t recent), and shows so little sign of going away. Unlike some analytic thinkers, who seem to want to abandon the analytic/continental distinction in favour of just ‘philosophy (but who then often go on to make clear that when they talk about ‘good philosophy’, they almost always mean ‘analytic’ philosophy), I don’t think the distinction can simply be discarded, since to do so is to blind oneself to the political realities that are at work
I think it is time to organize our own Continental philosophy carnival. As Malpas has confirmed, this distinction is not philosophical. Often analytic philosophers use either "family resemblance" or the metaphor of style. I do not think these apply directly. Indirectly sure. These might explain some of what is going on. Yet, the fact is that often what is seen as interesting to analytic conversations could not find purchase in a larger culture due to their neglect of the hermeneutic, phenomenological and pragmatic features of human life and action.
Take for example the entries in this month's carnival.
I have searched since October 2012. There hasn't been one article on a Continental author, not even to Protevi at New APPS that analytics know.
Moreover, Kenny Pearce has been a host of the Carnival several times over, and I feel that the the Carnival circulates in a network of blogs. This might explain how selection bias amongst its organizers avoid Continental philosophy while driving philosophy into oblivion. Having read through a lot of the Carnivals, one could possibly be convinced that there is an endemic of people worried about Plantinga!
Thursday, March 7, 2013
Phenomenological Theism and the Phenomenology of Moral Experience
I am presenting this at Steubenville’s Must Morality Be
Grounded in God? Conference. This is still very much a work in progress.
Consider what I call the Argument
from Moral Experience:
(1)
Moral facts are experienced as being objective and non-natural.
(2) The
best explanation of there being objective and non-natural moral facts is based
on phenomenological theism.
(3)
Phenomenological theism is the thesis that God is immanently revealed in moral
action.
(4)
Therefore, the experience of moral facts provides evidence for thinking theism
is true.
In the following lecture, I would like to assess the
argument from moral experience. My argument from moral experience is inspired
by a rendition of the typical Moral Argument
for God’s Existence:
(1’)
Moral facts are objective and non-natural.
(2’)
The best explanation of there being objective and non-natural moral facts is
theism.
(3’)
Therefore, the experience of moral facts provides evidence for thinking theism
is true.
The difference between these two arguments
is based on shifting the inference from the existence of God to the experience
of God. For the experience of God is immanent in moral action, and what we want
from morality can only acquire a sense and meaning from looking at the
structure of moral experience where God is felt. I will admit that part of this
analysis is inspired both by Scheler and Levinas, but my real ambition is to
get at the heart of the arguments as to why we might think Scheler and Levinas
correct in these matters. Let me speak to the organization of this essay.
First, I will explain the grounds for holding each premise,
and why I find it far superior to the Moral Argument for God’s Existence. Next,
I will offer phenomenological reasons why the conclusion follows from the
premises. In the Argument from Moral Experience, this will involve an in depth
analysis of premise (2), which is doing most of the work of the aforementioned
argument. Second, I will explain the motivations for why I focused on the
phenomenology of moral experience as a reason for concluding theism is true.
(1) could have been stated
different, such as “ (1’) Moral facts exist as objective and non-natural.” The
assertion of extant moral facts is harder to prove than the experience of moral
facts. The hard moral realist asserts the existence of an independently true
body of moral statements, which are true and treated very much the same way as
one might treat the belief that “Cats are mammals.” We treat the moral belief
that “People should be fair to each other” as suggesting something true for all
situations to which people would relate to each other. The reason why the hard
moral realist finds moral claims convincing is that they can oblige us from the
simple fact that they are true.
(1’) however proves too much. First, the hard moral realist
is metaphysically extravagant. He wants objectivity so much that he treats
moral claims like scientific claims. However, the truth conditions for such
objectivity distort how we experience values. First, we do not experience
values as an object of knowledge. They are felt deeply in intentional feeling.
Second, we do not assent to a proposition like a controlled scientific inquiry.
Instead, values are felt in exigent situations about the goods in question.
Moreover, the last two experiential reasons are motivations for why someone
might insist upon the truth of hard moral realism, but without a careful
phenomenological analysis of experience, the hard moral realist often is
self-serving in those features of experience he selects about experience that
motivates endorsing his extravagant metaethical position.
Let us look, then, at some features
of moral experience more carefully. If both you and I share a similar feeling,
we can intend the same value. Let us
use the oft-repeated example that you and I stand some distance from a group of
teenagers setting a cat on fire. There is nothing physical in that situation to
which we normally assign value, and yet we employ value-talk about the
situation. At this point, we are safe to assume that we experience the cat
burning as unnecessary suffering, and this action bears the value cruelty
beyond belief. If we asked the teenagers why they did it, we might try to find
some abuse in their background or some underlying motivation for why they set
the cat on fire, but looking for motivation of someone is different than the
felt-demand of value in that situation. We experience the wrongness of that
suffering deeply. From the experience, we begin to see that we have some
language to talk about how both you and I felt about that act. To see if we
have the same moral hunches and reactions, we talk to others that react
predictably similar to the same situation. Setting cats on fire is felt as cruel. From this common co-feeling
about the situation, we can conclude that there is some reliable objectivity in
how I and others feel and that nothing physical in that situation could account
for the feeling of cruelty manifest in our acts.
In (2), the phenomenology is the
explanation. Usually, metaethical positions import the assumptions about
reality as why we experience the world as we do, but phenomenological
description reverses this priority and looks to describe an experience of an
exemplar phenomenon before inferring ontological commitments. One might object
that this makes phenomenology, then, self-serving for what it wants from
ontology. However, I concede some of this without admitting the self-serving
nature of phenomenological method. Presupposing metaethical commitments about
moral experience before looking to experience itself is worse than looking to experience as a way to solve philosophical
problems. For the phenomenologist, taking experience for granted means removing
philosophy from the concerns of those that live it. In such distancing,
metaphysics can be employed to assert categories about experience that are not
found within experience at all, and such attempts could presuppose an ontology
about particular values. One motivation shared amongst phenomenologists is the want
for philosophy to concern itself with concrete matters of lived experience
rather than proposing any conceptualization removed from experience.
In moral experience, we experience
values as being on the backs of goods, deeds and persons. We feel these values
between us despite their lack of physical tangibility. We re-feel what someone
else feels and in that feeling, we are presented with value’s givenness.
Intentional feeling is correlated to a specific value-quality. Bliss fills our
whole personality with the Absolute value of the Holy. Our feeling of health is
connected to how our environment is given to us. In the highest value of the
Holy, our capacity to feel alongside others is renewed in the highest possible
way. We are instilled with a perspective completely outside of us that comes
unto us in ritual and religious experience more generally. Thus, when premise
(2) predicates “objective” and “non-natural” features of morality, these
qualities are aspects of experiencing intentional-feeling associated within
religion. God is the source to which we aim, and in aiming to that which is
completely Other we become oriented towards that which is pure difference in
our very action. We can easily welcome both widow and orphan to be fed by
having a renewed connection to Christ in the Eucharist. The singular unique
otherness of the other/person finds expression in both Levinas and Scheler. The
person is given to us as a possibility within the immanence of the suffering Other.
“Objective” here means “intersubjective” and is due to our capacity to re-feel
what others feel that binds us to others and the emanating presence where God
is felt. Before God, we are all unique. In relation to Him, I am Ed, a Ph.D.
graduate from SIU, born in New Jersey and raised in Western Pennsylvania. My
wife is Ashley, born in Youngstown Ohio and thankfully a Steelers fan. There is
nobody like her or me in existence. That’s the point. The objectivity takes on
a new sense within phenomenology. The objectivity in other moral philosophies
amounts to a substitutable other. Before Kantianism, we are all agents. Either you
or I ought to do the same thing in relation to the categorical imperative. Both
the non-formal ethics of Levinas and Scheler attempt to supplant this modernist
tendency of equalizing differences between people and insist upon the radical
unique otherness of the “person.” Ashley is not valuable due to species
membership, the fact that she is a rational agent or any other criterion beyond
herself. Instead, Ashley is absolutely unique, and it follows from her radical
uniqueness objectively that she is absolutely valuable. In fact, the
possibility to love another rests on accepting the singular uniqueness an-other
person.
Second, “non-natural” follows on the
heel of the singular uniqueness of persons. On this point, phenomenological
evidence is rather convincing. The fact that a person can never be objectified
or reduced to another category is what it means to be a person. Instead,
persons are of spirit. We cannot be
adequately categorized since we are beyond categorization and simultaneously we
are the source of that categorization. Persons are the source of meaning in the
world, and consequently, they cannot be derived from that which they engender.
Persons are not reducible to anything in the world. If intentional feeling
precedes all pre-volitional and pre-cognitive experience, then it is only from
the shared intentional capacity of persons that is responsible for why
experienced objects in life have meaning (and therefore value). Scheler’s later
metaphysics aims to articulate a view beyond the phenomenological but
preserving the insight of the person’s non-objectifiable spirit and at the same
time how persons and God participate in being together.
According to Scheler, the person encounters a world in its
vital urge. The vital urge reaches outward towards a goal in the world, and the
world is given to us in resistance. The vital urge is rarely satisfied and if
it attains its goal and the world conforms in some way to us, the world will
comply ever so briefly. Then, life will be given to us in this worldly
resistance once more, and we will not be sated. Within this movement, the
coming-to-be feltness of the resisting world is called value. In this way,
values are at the spiritual act-center of the person reaching out and filling
the content of our experience of actions, things and others. When we relate to another,
when we help another person, they – like us – encounter a life in which our
drives, energy and desire find resistance in the world around us. All reality
is given in resistance but capable of ever higher spiritualization. While
spirit is initially impotent to physically affect the world, we can experience
a calling within our vital-urges and learn to suspend their effect on us. Thus,
by suspending our attention to the vital-urge’s movement to a resisting world
and thereby suffering, human beings can apprehend a higher value than simply
their vital-urges. This happens when we act on love and within acting in love,
God stands between us and others, or what is meant in premise (3). We can
aspire to the level of spiritual feeling and values of Holiness. Thus, again
the point of religion is to open ourselves up towards the inherent
spiritualization in human life and realize it in all we do.
The point of phenomenological theism is not to replace the
sense of God has in His own right. Instead, accepting “(2’) The best
explanation of there being objective and non-natural moral facts is theism”
commits one to adopt the same phenomenological reasons inherent in the
Schelerian commitments I have explained here. Typically, an objective value is
one that can be demonstrated publically according to norms and justifications.
There are many possible ways we might do this. We might show that the consequences
in one outcome maximize better than in another outcome. We might show that one
course of action is more rational than another. However, the point matters not
how we justify a course of action. Instead, these approaches presuppose the
very phenomenology of experience underlying my motivation for emphasizing the
phenomenological insight over (2’). The utilitarian assumes value is already
knowable and that there is something like an impartial perspective to which
various outcomes can be assessed. The impartial standpoint in this secularly
committed approach relies upon an experience of thinking objectivity and
non-naturalism true. Values stand between people with respect to feeling; they
are irreducibly part of another’s experience, and yet we act upon them because
in participating in value the manifest benefit grows out of the presence of
that action. More secular theories might call this elevation of goodness in the
world acts of beneficence. In such a way, the intersubjectivity of what these
people take to be “objective” and valuable is wholly realized in action between
them and what becomes realized is a commitment to love the other. This love
manifests insofar as the utilitarian is more sophisticated in what she seeks to
maximize beyond mere hedonic calculation, but let’s leave this alone for now. As
long as the moral philosophy in question seeks to realize values through
action, there is something like a growth, a becoming, a presence of beneficence
underlying the affection such action brings. This is the experience in question
that is shared between secular and sacred approaches to values.
The growth and becoming of love
suspends the descending effect drives have upon us whereas love participates in
the intersubjective spirit of persons. For Scheler, persons can only be those
that can suspend the effect of drives upon us and reflectively bring into
awareness the act of suspending drives. Thus, persons and God are capable of
this, but when love takes on the highest value of the Holy, individuals become
given as absolutely other. There is no higher value than the absolute value of
the Holy. In this way, the intersubjective constitution of community can be
based upon a commitment to the Holy in the immanence of our firsthand
experience of Others. In our case, this commitment is the directedness of my
intentional act loves the other person as they are without imposing upon them
any objectification. Hence, objectification cannot be a source of making the
other a victim or reason for justifying abuse. Since spirit is pure
non-objectifiability, I can only leave the other be as a unique other before
God. In this way we can see the role of premise (3). The immanence of the
singular otherness comes by encountering them as each person is, singular and
unique. In the 20th century, the massive abuses of genocide arise
out of the tendency for governments and people to judge others through
objectified categories. A Jew can be less than human, so can Blacks in the
American South. The point is rather striking. By acknowledging God as a source
of immanent otherness underlying the otherness of people I encounter in life, I
adopt a philosophy incapable of re-presenting the singular uniqueness of
an-other. Instead, through God, we start with the recognition of singular
uniqueness and preserve the commitment to the non-objectifiability of human
beings first and foremost before all other commitments in philosophy. This
prohibition of objectification delimits the possibility of a metaphysics of
human beings at all.
Finally, “the experience of moral
facts” establishes a deduced relation to “thinking theism true.” I am
suspicious of metaphysics. Like Levinas, I want to supplant the tendency of
Western thinking to avoid “the logic of the same” or what Scheler repeatedly
calls “objectification.” The practical consequences of the 20th
century’s abuses have all subordinated the radical otherness of the person to
some category that dehumanizes. In fact, we might read this subordination of
the person to categories of metaphysical speculation in the tendency of
modernity to de-personalize the person. Instead, the first philosophy is not
metaphysics, but the ontology of the person. There is only one being that is
wholly other than I can re-present Him/It, and this is God. As Jean Valjean
sings towards the end of Le Miserable:
“To love the other person is to see the face of God.” In Schelerian speak, this
realization is the recognized givenness of the person within the experience of
their very uniqueness—what he calls “spirit.”
Of course, I broadened this insight, and claimed that “the
experience of moral facts” confirms “thinking theism true.” A moral fact could
be the recognition of a proposition that expresses that I owe others charity
when I can manage it at no cost to myself. Moral facts are propositionalized
positive and negative expressions of what I owe others. In our moral
imagination, we often imagine what it might mean to fulfill some mysterious
action and sometimes we want to universalize all others like the imagined other
and the imagined action as a basis for how others would act given the same set
of conditions. Yet, such an approach is dedicated to the objectification if the
intention may have been seeking out only what I ought to do in that situation.
I do not regard the others as anything other than those that again can be
substituted for another.
On the Possibility of Epistemic Ressentiment?
In this post, I would like to
expand the case for what I call epistemic resssentiment. The possibility of
epistemic ressentiment came to me
when I happened upon a forgotten passage in Scheler’s Ressentiment. In his Ressentiment.
Scheler traces all varieties of experience in which ressentiment occurs,
and proposes several initial forms in examples to arrive at the core of true
ressentiment proper. Towards the end of the first part, Scheler writes:
...a secret ressentiment underlies every way of thinking which attributes
creative power to mere negation and criticism. Thus modern philosophy I
deeply penetrated by a whole type of thinking which is nourished by ressentiment. I am referring to the view
that the “true” and the “given” is not that which is self-evident, but rather
that which is “indubitable” or “incontestable,” which can be maintained against
doubt and criticism. Let us also mention the principle of “dialectical method,”
which wants to produce not only non-A,
but even B through the negation of A. All the seemingly positive valuations and
judgments of ressentiment are hidden
devaluations and negations. Whenever convictions are not arrived at by direct
contact with the world and the objects themselves, but indirectly through
critique of the opinions of others, the processes of thinking are impregnated
with ressentiment. The establishment
of “criteria” for testing the correctness of opinions then becomes the most
important task. Genuine and fruitful criticism judges all opinions with
reference to the objects itself. Ressentiment criticism on the contrary,
accepts no “object” that has not stood the test of criticism.[1]
And two paragraphs later, Scheler informs us of the formal
structure of ressentiment itself:
The formal structure of ressentiment expression is always the
same: A is affirmed, valued, and praised not for its own intrinsic quality, but
with the unverbalized intention of denying, devaluating, and denigrating B. A
is “played off” against B.[2]
In these two passages, I do not intend an extensive
exegesis. Instead, I will expand what Scheler means in order to offer an account
of epistemic ressentiment. I will distingusi two varieties: Metaphysical
Lifeworld Ressentiment and Interlocutor Ressentiment. I find difficulty with
the latter and insist on the plausibility of the former.
In the extensive passage, Scheler
introduces the modern period and dearth of trust in self-evidency. For him, the
condition of modern philosophy is one in which the true and the given cannot be
experienced at all, let alone be the subject matter of a knowledge claim.
Modernity exemplified in Descartes offers only the inner working of
subjectivity as a measure for any knowledge claim. A knowledge claim must be
inconstestable and indubitable. For Scheler, this Cartesian emphasis removes
the knowledge claim from putting us into contact with the world and its objects
in the right way. For Scheler, only
direct contact with the world and objects themselves serve as a normative
principle for making knowledge claims. If a philosophical system does not have
contact with the world and its objects in the right way, then those knowledge
claims become questionable. In Cartesian thought, the world and its objects are
divided into the realm of extension and the workings of the subjectivity where
one feels the valence of self-reference as a source of validation for all
knowledge claims. Yet, what is really happening is that the subject is the
affirming the value of itself to deny and denigrate the realm of objects.
Descartes’s cogito plays up the
self-referential function as a measure to which all other claims must be
grounded upon, yet the privilege of one is made at the expense of nature in an
unconvincing division between thinking substance and extended substance.
Therefore, any philosophical system that has its source and validation in the
subject cannot tease out the difference between itself and genuine knowledge
claims without succumbing to epistemic ressentiment. In the preceding passage,
Scheler describes two forms of epistemic ressentiment: 1) Metaphysical
Lifeworld Ressentiment and 2) Interlocutor Ressentiment. Let me first take up
Metaphysical Lifeworld Ressentiment.
The concern for a test in the
Cartesian sense, the test of indubitability, is a case of epistemic
ressentiment of asserting the value of the subject over and against the world.
I call this Metaphysical Lifeworld Ressentiment. In truth, any philosophical
system – as is the case with both empiricism and rationalism is secretly
“nourished by ressentiment.” These
examples embody a system that introduces the unnecessary division between
intentional acts and objects. As I have said earlier, when Scheler observes a
dearth of the world and object leading one’s own epistemic efforts, this
commitment is a residuum of Scheler’s phenomenology of “spiritual seeing.” Such
spiritual seeing requires only that a commitment to experience of acts and
objects be described in tandem with each other.
…phenomenology is neither the name
of a new science nor a substitute for the word philosophy; it is the name of an
attitude of spiritual seeing in which one can see or experience something which
otherwise remains hidden, namely, a realm of facts of a particular kind. I say
attitude, not method. A method is a goal-directed procedure for thinking about facts…before they have
been fixed by logic, and second, of a procedure of seeing… That which is seen
and experienced is given only in the seeing and experiencing of the act itself,
in its being acted out; it appears in that act and only in it. [3]
In this way, we can
easily understand why Scheler urges the return of both the “world” and “object”
in the long passage after mentioning Descartes. The object is “that which is
seen and experienced is given only in the seeing and experiencing of the act
itself, in its being acted out; it appears in the act and only in it.” In Ressentiment, the lack of
phenomenological content of acts-in-relation-to-the-world is lost in
Descartes’s succumbing to epistemic ressentiment. The real open question
remains, however. In proposing this initial form of epistemic ressentiment,
does Scheler advance an implicit commitment to interpret all
non-phenomenological forms of philosophizing as guilty of epistemic
ressentiment? I will return to this question later. For now, I think we are
ready for a formal statement of epistemic ressentiment (ER) for both
Metaphysical Lifeworld Ressentiment and Interlocutor Ressentiment:
ER: is an epistemic act or system of epistemic acts
constituting an entire philosophical system in which the valuation of a
knowledge claim A is affirmed not for the intrinsic quality of honoring the
intentional relation and expressing truth, but to denigrate another knowledge
claim B or system of epistemic acts consistent with B.
Next, let
me transition to Interlocutor Ressentiment. We can see this definition in the
second matter before us, dialectical method. In that method, it is usually
accepted that an Interlocutor can put forth a conclusion resting on several
premises and another epistemic agent can propose their own counter-argument as
to why the first argument is either unsound in its content or invalid in its
structure. I largely accept these norms given that adherence to these norms
produces better philosophical positions than those that might ignore these
norms of good reasoning. However, there are times when these norms are not
guided by a search for truth, but are instrumental tools in the critique of
opinions. In some ways, the social experiences at some APA meetings tend to
devolve into harsh exchanges that feign civility between interlocutors. In
those instances, argumentation – like subject/object split systems in the
modern period, are capable of being more concerned with the “establishment of
criteria for testing the correctness of opinions” than “fruitful criticism”
judging opinion in relation to the “object
itself.” When Scheler mentions
the “object itself,” he is expressing a concern for the phenomenological
object. Phenomenological seeing is, therefore, a normative principle at work
here. The whatness of the phenomenon guides our insight of the object
correlating to the epistemic act in immanent intuition. The object opens itself
up to our epistemic act. Insofar as we are valuing truth itself in the
epistemic act, the object must attend the act to get it right.
Scheler is
pretty clear that true ressentiment requires two elements. First, the person
feeling ressentiment must be impotent, and incapable of releasing the emotive
discharge of ressentiment. Moreover, the feeling of ressentiment requires
comparison with others—typically in the form of envy and jealously. From the
following two passages, the comparison between subject/object split modern
thinkers and those who use the dialectic method, neither envy nor jealously
seem especially apt for what I have been talking about here. For the modern
thinkers, the comparison is made from a stable subject against an indifferent
world of objects. The epistemic acts of modern thinkers in subject-object
epistemologies are more concerned with logical consistency than letting direct
contact with the world and objects guide understanding. In this way, modern
thinkers never understand the primal-urge drives and affective instincts at
work in a particular metaphysical system. In fact, Scheler and Nietzsche would
agree that only through philosophical reflection can the very unconscious
motives and factors shaping a metaphysical system and cultural lifeworld be
brought to the foreground. These unconscious motives can be a source of value
delusion in which delusive preferences are promoted by inhering in the very
heart of the metaphysical system for an entire cultural ethos. An ethos for
Scheler is a particular understanding of the objective value-rankings in which
an individual and culture may have a true or false ranking of the eternal
value-rankings. For instance, a cultural ethos may prefer pleasure over the
epistemic truth, and this value-preferencing while not right when measured
against Scheler’s value-rankings may be ingrained in their lifeworld. As such,
these ingrained tendencies and responses underly the entire metaphysical
lifeworld ethos. In Descartes, for instance, all persons are reduced to a
homogenous universal rational subject that with the use of reason will come to
be a “master and possessor of nature.” Clearly, Scheler thinks that the
function of phenomenological reflection brings the immanent relation between
the person and the primordial feeling of the knowledge claim and its object
into full view, even beyond the particular ethos in which one is living.
Otherwise, a person may be deceived by the value-delusion that redirects the
drives, instincts and desires implicitly shaping the understanding of a
knowledge claim and its object into a misapprehension of how values are ranked
objectively. For this very reason, Resisting epistemic ressentiment occurs when
persons value truth, justice and the beautiful over the particular ethos that
lowers these values of the object to serve some other purpose.
In the
dialectical method of philosophy, the social experience can serve other
purposes beyond truth. In some ways, Scheler’s brief allusion through the
powers of negation of non-A and the
denunciation of B seem suffuse with an awareness of the problems in social
epistemology in which interest/belief and power/knowledge are intimately
interwoven. Like before, the mere criticism of an opinion without reference to
the object employs the same phenomenological norm as before. Without being
guided by the act-object correlating structure, the use of dialectical method
can conceal what is truly occurring. Notice, however, in the formal definition
of ressentiment Scheler regards the relation of the negation of A as a silent
“unverbalized” devaluation of B, even if B is not strictly mentioned. In the
much the same way as before, the devaluation of someone else’s opinion involves
here the comparison of one’s belief to that of another. The social reality can
be a dialogic exchange that occurs in speech or writing. Using the dialogic
exchange in a dialectic method entails a social act. For Scheler, social acts
entail the presence of the others in order for them to be realized. The dialectic
method, therefore, is social and intersubjective as the earlier example of a
metaphysical system. The introduction of a test of correctness conceals that
the exchange between two or more interlocutors, yet ressentiment is a movement
of psychic energy that once internalized and repressed lashes out in the
epistemic act shared with others. In ressentiment, one person becomes devalued
by the other in an exchange. On the surface, this epistemic ressentiment is
difficult to see. The social aspect of the epistemic ressentiment is not
concerned with truth but through devaluation and negation. In devaluation and
negation, a silent intention is unconcerned with truth. The devalued person
illustrates the stupidity found in the heart of his personal core beliefs. The
devalued person and his beliefs are regarded as a cause for why others do not
accept my beliefs.
We are now
in a position to evaluate both types. First, I will mention the problem with
the Interlocutor Ressentiment given in Scheler’s exposition of the dialectic
method. Here, Scheler’s case is a bit overstated, nor is Scheler’s agitation of
the modern period and its inability to allow evidence through intuition freely
given. These are insights that need more refinement, and I find them
insufficiently articulated in epistemic ressentiment. In the dialectic method,
arguments are scrutinized by offering up counterexamples and reasons that might
falsify a premise in the argument. Moreover, someone might show that the
argument contradicts itself, the conclusion is not supported by the premises or
any other number of argumentative mechanics. These argumentative mechanics are
accepted as norms for philosophizing generally speaking. Given that philosophy
inquires into conceptual questions that common sense, faith or science alone
cannot grasp, the application of dialectic method and the logical norms ensure
that philosophizing can arrive at truth. In this way, logical norms and
dialectic method can conceal some silent intention unverbalized intention for
epistemic ressentiment, but it would be very hard for the activity alone in the
critique of mere opinions to conceal such intentions due to the wide range of
those logical norms associated with dialectic method. Even phenomenological
seeing requires logical consistency and the avoidance of contradiction when the
phenomenologist describes the act-object intentional structure. These are norms
that govern phenomenology as well as underscore dialectic method. As such,
direct phenomenological contact with the world and objects is not an entirely
reliable indicator when epistemic ressentiment occurs between two interlocutor as
an ability to honor the truth as Scheler seems to imply here. What I will say
is that phenomenological seeing is necessary for detecting epistemic
ressentiment just not sufficient. Not everyone engaged in argumentation or
claiming knowledge in relation to someone else is interested in honoring the
truth as they should, but for those that value truth above lower values in
Scheler’s rankings are immune from epistemic ressentiment. Epistemic
ressentiment is better understood as a value-delusion.
If
epistemic ressentiment is better understood as a form of value-delusion, then a
revision of my formal definition is required. Particularly, I must revise what
ambiguously appears as “denigration” and qualify what I mean by it. The
denigration of B is a distortion of what is co-given or co-felt and like the
metaphysical lifeworld ressentiment, there is a distortion on the part of what
I know from how the cultural lifeworld constitutes my knowledge in both the
affective and cognitive dimensions. Both these experiences embody how a
particular ethos can reveal the value-preferences of an entire culture. In
other words, the case for epistemic ressentiment makes sense as an opening up
the possibility of what will become Scheler’s Principles of a Sociology of Knowledge. While I do not have space
to develop the following thought, it should be shared. I conjecture that the pursuit of real factors in epistemic acts
fosters epistemic ressentiment, and the pursuance of ideal factors avoids it.
Let me transition to Metaphysical Lifeworld Ressentiment.
Scheler’s
insights for Metaphysical Lifeworld Ressentiment are better developed. Still, I
would like to pause and return to my earlier rhetorical question: In proposing
this initial form of epistemic ressentiment, does Scheler advance an implicit
commitment to interpret all non-phenomenological forms of philosophizing as
guilty of epistemic ressentiment? From the two brief passages here, that might
seem likely. However, we must remember that Scheler’s phenomenological method
is one of seeing, and it privileges intuitive evidence to gain access into the
primordial affectivity, value-structures and the beliefs foregrounded by them.
In that way, there are other possible methods one may employ to arrive at the
same insights for Scheler. Pragmatism brings into reflection the cultural
milieu of a particular problem or valuation in much the same way. For
pragmatists are concerned with how some ideas, conceptions and beliefs
functionalize in the cultural lifeworld, and James in particular is aware that
metaphysical beliefs are motivated very much by our practical and aesthetic
interests though pragmatism would never propose an eternal value-ranking.
In this
short post, I have come full circle, and while not a refined reflection,
certainly we can see that epistemic ressentiment is a possibility, but the
metaphysical and lifeworld ethos must already saturate the domain of an
epistemic agent. Moreover, the sociology of knowledge, even if not Scheler’s
but possibly Mannheim might better articulate the relationship between social
aspects of knowledge and epistemic acts. I am digressing and should end this
post.
[1]
Max Scheler, Ressentiment trans. W.
W. Holdheim (New York: Glencoe, 1961), 67-68.
[2]
Scheler, Ressentiment, 68.
[3] Max
Scheler, “Phenomenology and the Theory of Cognition” in Selected Philosophical Essays (Evanston, IL: Northwestern
University Press, 1973): 136-201. Scheler, Phenomenology,
137-138 here. Emphasis mine.
Wednesday, March 6, 2013
An Oddity of The Left?
I have many friends on the academic Left. These span the gambit between ultra-revolutionary classical Marxists to tame Habermasians that only want to cultivate communicative praxis in political discourse. In this post, I ask that you allow me to indulge in thinking there are soft Leftists and hard Leftists. Hardly anybody in my experience is a Hard Leftist. Hard Leftists were perhaps famous during the 1960/70ss when counter-cultural politics occupied a height unparalleled since that time. Now, Hard Leftists are simply novelty, an interesting oddity on campus, and I have come to think that even the very successful academic careers tend to tame Hard Leftists into Softer Leftists. To be a hard Leftist requires a constant passion to address systemic wrongs or a series of wrongs usually through an overarching unified explanation (Marxism of some variety), and the constant ire of their philosophical and political passion is unnerving to many. You may have observed this when they teach, but then the same professor goes home in their Bentley they bought from what they make at a tier 1 research school.
Softer Leftists simply only want to engage in a critique. They see their efforts at clarifying existing power structures, but often they do not live what they teach. The disconnect, however, is explainable by their softer attitudes and the want to open the eyes of whom they teach. They are affecting culture in a slower way. The Hard Leftist desires revolution of some variety; the Soft Leftist would welcome a revolution of awareness. Both, however, never have any productive positive solution to offer.
Strangely enough, the only philosophers that offer solutions as part of their routine are applied ethicists and thinkers of a pragmatic bent. This strikes me as odd. Some of my Leftist friends in both camps are so upset at the world that they continue on upset in the maddening fixation fueled by critique, but they never reach beyond critique or when they call for revolution, they are constantly calling for activism about something different each time.
Subscribe to:
Posts (Atom)